[Commons-Law] Free Software and Market Relations
Jeebesh Bagchi
jeebesh at sarai.net
Tue Jan 6 03:38:57 IST 2004
http://www.oekonux.org/texts/index.html
Free Software and Market Relations
Raoul Victor
The Economic Reality of Free Software
Free Software and Market Society
Free Software and the Law of Value, or the Revolutionary Possibilities of Free
Software
The Ideology of the Founders of Free Software
Germs of Non-market Relations
What Marx and History Say
"Germs"?
Insufficiency and Validity of Marxism
New Questions
The following is a translation (amateur) of one part of a debate that took
place on a Francophone internationalist communist listserv. Marx quotes are
taken from standard English translations. There is only one other note on
translation: the use of the word gratuite and its derivations. There is no
direct translation for it, because it is more than ?gratuity,? which sounds
like restaurant lingo, and more than ?freedom,? which sounds
bourgeois-revolutionary. The idea is of a principle to replace exchange
value; as exchange value is to commodities under capitalism, gratuite is to
products of use value in communism.
In the text "Germs of non-commercial relationships in the midst of the most
modern capitalism", I attempted to show that the specificities of software,
in particular the capacity of being reproducible at an insignificant cost,
thus also the more and more important and determinant place which it is
called to take in practically all the processes of production, are
constitutive of material conditions that open new perspectives for the
possibility of a society of abundance, and thus of a post-capitalist society.
I also tried to show in evidence the "non-market" character of the principles
and relations which rule free software, thus also the crucial role that this
reality could play in the elaboration and diffusion of the revolutionary
project.
In his contribution of June 29, 2002, JC [another participant on the listserv]
raises a series of interesting objections to these ideas. The object of this
text is to respond to them.
JC tackles two principal questions. The first, he summarizes as follows: "I
want to attempt to establish that 'free software' does not avoid, in its
economic reality and in the ideology of its founders, market relations"; the
second: "I wonder about the idea that, in the midst of capitalism, by way of
new technological developments, 'the germs of non-market relations' could be
born."
To respond, I will attempt to follow JC in his questioning.
To tackle the specific question of free software, JC begins by making some
remarks of a more general order.
In posing a riddle--"From whom are these lines?"--in order to prepare his
surprise, JC cites a researcher and manager of the French government (Bernard
Lang), who makes statements analogous to those I made. {Informatics
programs," wrote Lang, "immaterial in essence, tend to reverse the traditions
of commerce. Conception and development aside, their production and
distribution costs can be marginal, quasi-zero.... Free software announces a
major change in civilization: the advent of a society of abundance." JC does
not follow this explicitly to its conclusion. But what could he conclude?
That such a statement is false because it's made by a man of the
establishment? For Lang, "the major change in civilization" of which he
speaks is evidently not the surpassing of capitalism, but an amelioration of
the same (we revisit further below the defenders of free software as a means
of renovating capitalism). That does not prevent one making a statement of
evidence, of a reality that "tends to reverse the traditions of commerce."
The intrinsic tendency of software to escape the laws of the market is a
reality that the new market-makers (practically industrialists), of illegal
copies of informatics products (business software, video-games, music discs,
or films, etc.) confirm and exploit daily...or the agents of the state
charged with suppressing this sort of attack on the market laws.
That which is surprising is not that establishment types could confirm the
anti-market nature of certain characteristics of software. This nature is
evident as soon as you think a little about it (we shall come back to this,
also). That which does not cease to surprise me is the resistance of numerous
Marxists to this fact. It goes back to Marx, though, to have well established
the mechanisms of market exchange and the possibility of its surpassing by
the appearance of conditions of abundance.
Making a second general remark, JC takes up on his account an argument often
employed by Marxists to deny the fundamentally new character of contemporary
technological evolution.
"I share," writes JC, "the remark made by RGF at the June 15 conference, which
signaled that this capacity of reproduction, not only quasi-gratuiticity, but
gratuiticity period, already existed in the domain of the results of
scientific research. And thus free software, however much it corresponds to
this ideal (sometimes for harm, as, for example, with the military) of free
reproduction and gratuiticity of the results of scientific research, bring
nothing very new onto the terrain."
The "free and gratuitistic reproduction of the results of scientific research"
is not a so generalized reality; in part, that which one calls "the hacker
ethic" of the creators of the first free software forged itself in combat in
the universities against the pressure of the administration to commercialize
the products of their research. And one knows, at such a point, patents
constitute a true barrier against the universality of scientific knowledge.
But it is true that the essence of this knowledge, under the form of texts,
theorems, rules, equations, etc., finds itself in the public domain, and that
anyone can draw from it at will. In this sense, effectively, there is
something in common between the qualities of free software and that of
scientific knowledge.
But science is not useful, does not have a direct use value, but for a very
narrow part of society. Generally, it does not enter except indirectly into
the process of production or consumption. Software can, on the contrary, take
the form of means of production or consumption, directly useful on the
assembly line, or for the manager of an office, for example. It can also
constitute a means of direct consumption, like with films or games. That to
which software permits everyone to have access, by rendering them freely and
gratuitistically reproducible, is not only equations or laws, but direct
instruments of production and goods of common consumption. The number of
goods, or the part of goods, capable of being an object of this gratuitistic
reproduction is limited only by the scale and measure in which the capacity
to digitalize the process of production and goods of consumption develops
itself. That which is "new" is not little. That is the possibility of the
gratuiticity, not only in the area of the university and the laboratory, but
in the heart of social production, there where, daily, economic and social
relations create themselves.
Constantly, in the perspective of establishing that software and informatics
in general "do not bring anything very new," JC echoes the questions of Henri
S on "whether the fundamental industrial revolution was not that of today,
that of informatics, but that of yesterday, electricity." Independent of the
question of the definition of the term "industrial revolution," one can
always say that without electricity there would have been neither electronics
nor informatics, and there can be no doubt that the generalization of the use
of electricity transformed also the process of production as much as modes of
social life. That is not to denigrate what was perceived by Kropotkin and
Lenin (socialism is the soviets plus electricity) as an element which would
contribute qualitatively new methods to the creation of the conditions of a
society of abundance. But that does not remove any of the importance of the
novelty contained in the new technologies. Electricity remains a good
submitted to scarcity. It cannot be "freely reproducible." Once produced and
consumed, a kilowatt-hour is no more. On the contrary, the means of
production which take the form of software could, themselves, be "consumed"
and reproduced indefinitely without any significant cost. The contribution of
the electronic revolution is not situated solely on the terrain of the
exceptional growth of the productivity of labor. It also places itself on a
qualitative level, at the base of the economic edifice itself, that of market
exchange, of the law of value, rendered futile when confronted by goods that
intrinsically tend to escape from shortage. In this sense, the contribution
of the new information and communications technologies cannot be reduced to
that of electricity.
But, JC's principal critique is, justly, about the reality of this questioning
of exchange. In taking the most "advanced" case, that of free software, he
attempts to show that it "does not escape from market relations." For that,
he develops his arguments firstly at the level of their "economic reality,"
and secondly, at the level of "the ideology of the founders." I tackle these
two levels in the same order.
The Economic Reality of Free Software
Free Software and Market Society
On the economic level, the arguments proposed by JC essentially concern the
relations of free software with the capitalist environment. He shows how,
around free software like Linux, a series of commercial companies gravitate,
who live from the sale of services facilitating the installation and the use
of the software, those that lead to "what one could call sometimes a pretty
high invoice for a Linux installation." JC illustrates again the influence of
the market environment on free software in citing examples of its use by
state institutions: for national French education, for research into the
reduction of "costs of formation of the workforce"; by the French and
American armies, which "are wary, for security reasons, of software over
which they don't have complete control." He also invokes the existence of a
"group lobbying in favor of Linux and free software," very active among
circles of the French political class. He states that certain of the creators
of free software are paid for this task by commercial enterprises, and thus
that those who "benevolently" made it, often with "lost hours," get a salary.
And last but not least, JC puts in relief the support provided free software
by certain enterprises: "But," he writes, "free software is supported by a
series of enterprises involved in the information market, that have an
interest in the destruction of Microsoft's monopoly over software, and in the
first ranks of them: IBM."
In concluding, JC says: "Free software is not a "freely" reproducible good; if
there is a contradiction in the kingdom of market laws, it is the very
classical one between the position of the monopoly acquired by Microsoft and
the other enterprises in the same sector; it is not a revolt of the
productive forces against the relations of production which they have
engendered, but the revolt of information enterprises against a monopoly
situation that is contrary to the general interests of capital."
However, all these facts show, not that free software does not possess a
non-market character, but that it is immersed in a market world. Any of the
aspects of economic reality cited by JC do not concern the non paying,
gratuitistic nature of free software itself. They show how merchants are able
to make a profit in selling products connected with free software. But, it
improper for JC to deduce that "free software is not gratuitistic software."
The paying character of that which can be connected to Linux does not remove
any of the perfectly gratuitistic character of Linux itself. JC states also
that recourse to free software is interesting economically to commercial
enterprises or state administrations because it is synonymous with the
reduction of costs. But that does nothing but show the reality of its
gratuiticity (or quasi-gratuiticity), denied by JC, because it is just
because they are gratuitistic that they entail a diminishment of costs. As
for to the argument citing the use of free software by armies, it only gives
evidence of the effectiveness of certain of its technological advantages,
without dealing with the gratuitistic nature of the software. Finally, the
idea that the development of free software would be essentially the product
of "the revolt of information enterprises against a monopoly situation
[Microsoft] that is contrary to the general interests of capital," is also
excessively reductionist, and ignores the importance that some free software
are taking. It is true that if IBM and other computer manufacturers
participate in the development of free software, and prescribe Linux as the
OS for certain of their machines, that is, in large part, to emancipate
themselves from their dependence vis a vis Microsoft. But, the same fact,
that the top global information enterprise should be forced to have recourse
to free software translates into the superiority of this type of product and
the inevitability of its development.
The still small world of free software evidently does not escape the commodity
environment in which it lives. Why would the merchants who dominate the
society deprive themselves of the technical and economic advantages of this
new type of product? What would forbid it from becoming like a weapon in the
permanent war among them, on the military level or that of the struggle for
control of the market?
The question that poses itself is that of knowing whether this market
environment extinguishes the non-market character of free software and
condemns it to being nothing more than a tool of reinforcement of the
dominant system, of "regularization of market relations," like JC says.
History furnishes examples of the coexistence of two types of economic
relations, in particular during the course of the period in which a new mode
of production is developing in the midst of the old society, as in the case
for capitalism in the midst of feudalism, or of feudalism in the midst of
ancient slavery. In these two cases, like I have implied in the text
criticized by JC, "there is a phenomenon which sees the ruling class of the
old system being forced to have recourse to products of a mode of production
which is antagonistic to its own. "
In the ancient Roman slave empire, the colonat, a first form of feudalism in
which the slave is emancipated and transformed into a free colonus but
subordinated to new economic obligations, progressively develops itself up to
the point of becoming the most important mode of production in the late Roman
Empire of the 3rd century. The slave state drew its profits, not always
easily, from the growth of productivity that the new economic relations
brought, by levying ever-heavier taxes on their production and even in
transforming some of their own slaves into coloni.
In the coexistence between feudalism and capitalism, recourse by the old
dominant class, the feudal masters, to the means furnished by the new
relations, capitalism, which had developed themselves in the cities and by
commerce, is even more spectacular. The feudal crusades, which led to the
extension of the European fiefdoms all the way up to the Orient, of the 11th
to the 13th century (creation of the Kingdom of Jerusalem, of the
principality of Antioch, etc.), would not have been possible but for recourse
to the forms of capitalist production, which, in cities like Venice, produced
the boats which transported the feudal armies and Oriental booty. It was in
using the capitalist financial wealth developing particularly in the cities
of Genoa and Venice that the European masters found the means of financing
their imperialist enterprises in the Holy Lands. In France, since the 12th
century, the monarchy extended its power at the expense of the large regional
feudal masters by leaning on the cities, in which the bourgeoisie and
capitalist relations would develop, and to whom the king granted specific
privileges. The feudal masters o f all Europe could, during centuries,
continue to draw their profit from the capitalist commerce which was
developing, not only in procuring goods otherwise unattainable, but also in
withdrawing innumerable taxes of passage for the commerce that crossed their
fiefdoms.
What can one deduce in relation to the debate that concerns us? Firstly, that
the fact that the old dominant class draws profit from the products of new
social relations does not remove their novelty, their antagonistic character.
Secondly, that the economic and political power of the old dominant class
inevitably constitutes a restriction of the development of the new relations:
There had to be the bourgeois political revolutions to clear the feudal taxes
of passage for the development of commerce, for example. But, thirdly, that,
because of the fact that the new relations contain a new productive capacity,
the old dominant class is forced to have recourse to them, even if it is
nothing more than as a partial means, marginal at first. In so doing, that
class stimulates their development. (The feudal crusades, for the Italian
cities that contributed to them, were a source of the first capitalist
prosperity.)
Even today the use of free software by commercial enterprises or by state
administrations does not destroy its non-market nature. The states multiply
new legislation and repressive bodies to stop the attacks on copyright and
other foundations of property and capitalist profit, put in harms way by the
logic of free software. But the same states, like all capitalist enterprises,
are at some point obliged to have recourse to it. And this can do nothing but
stimulate its development.
Free Software and the Law of Value, or the Revolutionary Possibilities of Free
Software
JC's arguments have led us to the terrain of the relations of free software
with the market milieu. But the central question, on the economic plane, is
to comprehend by what "internal" logic free software is by nature non-market,
non-capitalist, and contains revolutionary possibilities. JC, unfortunately,
does not tarry at this point, except to reject it as an illusion, and send
the problem back to the reality of market competition: "My initial argument,"
he writes, "portrays mostly as an illusion that in free software there could
be seen new 'revolutionary' possibilities, beginning with their reality in
the play of market competition."
It suffices to remember what the market relations are, and their specificity
in capitalism, to understand how free software is their negation.
Market relations rest on exchange. Exchange is to acquire or to cede something
by means of a counter-party. The barter is in the most elementary form of it.
A good or a service is directly furnished in exchange for another. The market
relationship establishes that this exchange must follow the rule of equality,
the good furnished must possess a market value, exchange value, equivalent to
that of the good received. The law of value measures this value by means of
the labor time socially necessary to produce the good exchanged. The use of a
particular commodity as a universal equivalent, money (livestock in certain
ancient societies, in which the term "pecuniary," of or regarding pecus,
which in Latin means cattle; eventually metallic pieces, notes, bank money,
etc.), thus authorizes a flexibility unlimited by exchange, and offers the
possibility of accumulating value, dead labor. Capitalism constitutes the
most fully achieved form of exchange and of market relations, thus it extends
its domination to all domains of social life, in the first place to labor
power, which it transforms into a commodity by means of wage-relationships.
But the logic of free software situates itself outside of exchange itself.
When someone "takes" free software off the Internet, even if its production
required millions of hours of labor, there is nothing given in exchange. One
takes without furnishing any counterpart. The software furnished is not
exactly "given," in the classic sense of the term, since the provider still
has it after the taker has helped himself. (In this sense, the term of
"economy of the gift" that certain people use apropos free software is
incorrect.) There is indeed the transmission of a good, but with neither loss
of possession nor counter-party. The foundation of capitalism, exchange, is
absent. In this sense already, free software has an intrinsically
anti-capitalist, potentially revolutionary nature.
But it does not suffice to be "anti-capitalist" to be revolutionary
historically, as shown by the nostalgic anti-capitalist thought of a less
dehumanized past. If free software possesses a revolutionary nature, that is
also because its method rests on the concrete will to liberate the powers
contained in the new techniques of information and communication. This method
is the result of the simple acknowledgment on t he part of several
universities that certain aspects of market relations gravely impeded their
utilization. If this happens with electronic techniques and not with other
techniques of production, that is not only because the scientific ethic
contains non-market aspects but also because, and above all, in this domain
it is very easy, and costs nothing, to ignore the market laws. In this sense,
the method of free software situates itself inside the movement of history
(in the measure in which the development of society's productive forces
constitutes the only dimension that, "in the last instance," permits one to
detect a direction in it), in the direction of the surpassing of capitalism.
The Ideology of the Founders of Free Software
The creators and defenders of free software-are they aware of this reality?
For JC, the question doesn't come up : ?The texts of the founders of the FSF
[Free Software Foundation],? he writes, ?confirm that they place themselves
entirely in the context of market capitalism.? And, to defend this thesis, JC
gives some citations:
Stallman [founding member of the FSF] exposes the ideological and social
references of free software: ?The free software movement was founded in 1984,
but its inspiration comes from the ideas of 1776: liberty, community and
voluntary cooperation. That is what leads to free enterprise, to the liberty
of expression and to free software. Like in the case of "free enterprise" and
"freedom of expression," the term "free" in the term "free software" makes
reference to liberty, not to price...? Against Microsoft, Stallman writes:
?But the absence of defense is not the American way. On the grounds of
courage and freedom, we defend our liberty with the GNU GPL [the GNU General
Public License],? and goes on to conclude that: ?Property rights were
conceived in order to advance the well- being of mankind.? 1Scroll downwards
JC thus presents one of the more well-known creators and defenders of free
software as an advocate of prices and private property. The reality of the
hacker's conceptions is much more complex and contradictory. To be convinced,
it just requires putting some of the citations JC gives into context. Thus,
at the end of the phrase, ?the term "free" in the term "free software" makes
reference to liberty, not to price,? Stallman wrote : ?More specifically, it
signifies that you have the liberty to study, to modify, and to redistribute
the software that you use.? But, having the right to redistribute software is
to have the right to transmit it gratuitistically, without price, ignoring
property rights and copyright; studying and modifying software expresses that
it's not to be secret, protected, like all ?proprietary? software. Some lines
further, the same Stallman wrote: ?We cannot establish a community of liberty
in the world of proprietary software, in which each program has its master.
We will constitute a new world in cyber-space...? And the tidbit JC cited on
property rights are in the following context: ?My opinions on copyright would
take an hour to explain, but a general principle applies: One cannot justify
the negation of important public liberties. Like Abraham Lincoln put it,
'each time there is a conflict between the rights of man and the rights of
property, the rights of man must prevail.' Property rights were conceived in
order to advance the well-being of mankind and not as an excuse to scorn
them.? Stallman effectively defends property rights, but on the condition
that they do not hurt ?the rights of man?... which is not very simple: If the
right not to starve, for example, is a right of man, the right of property
over the means of production must be abolished. In another more well-known
text by Stallman, The GNU Manifesto, he writes: ?Extraction of money from the
users of a program by restraining their use of the program is destructive,
because, for the sake of cash, it reduces the amount of wealth humanity can
draw from the program. When choice is deliberately restrained, the harmful
consequences are a deliberate destruction.? 2Scroll downwards
The defense of the use and generalization of free software leads logically to
the defense of non-market, thus non-capitalist principles, such principles as
gratuiticity, non-property. But this does not imply that one would
obligatorily deny the validity of market principles in all domains. The
founders of free software do not pretend to destroy the capitalist world.
They want to create, in the world of communications and information, a ?
cyberspace...a community of liberty,? to use Stallman's words, on the side,
outside, ?the world of proprietary software, in which each program has its
master.?
From this inevitably flow contradictions, like when Stallman demands
simultaneously capitalist free enterprise and a community of liberty with
neither masters nor market exchange. That expresses a contradictory reality
which already exists and develops itself within society because of the
coexistence and interpenetration of the world of free software with modern
capitalism. The Internet is a striking illustration. The principal software
on which it depends for functioning is free software. Without it, the
?network of networks? could not function. However, the Internet has not
ceased to become an indispensable instrument for capitalist, commercial,
financial, administrative, police, etc., transactions, and that on a
planetary level.
The question of the relation to capitalism is at the heart of the divisions
that split the world of the defenders of free software. 3Scroll downwards For
some of them, like the partisans of the Open Source Initiative, founded in
1998 by Eric Raymond, free software could be one of the instruments for
ameliorating and reinforcing capitalism. Stefan Merten, of Oekonux, says that
he would have called it ? 'Free Software for Business'-or something like
that.? 4Scroll downwards Bernard Lang, one of the authors of the book Free
Software, cited many times by JC, is part of this tendency. He goes up to the
point of defending recourse to free software as a means of reinforcing and
defending European capital confronted with American competition. The frame of
spirit of the partisans of Stallman's FSF is quite different. Even if one
found a number of differences according to their degree of opposition to the
market world, there are general approaches more interested in developing a
?space of liberty ? than in cooperating with market enterprises. It is true
that opposition to Microsoft, which has become a diabolical symbol of the
will to monopoly, attacked even by the justice of the American state, plays a
very important role and sustain the illusion of the defense of a market world
without trusts. But there are also tendencies that go much further. Marx said
that Protestantism could not make a radical critique of Catholicism without
making a self-critique. It is the same with the critique of Microsoft : It
cannot be radical without a critique of capitalism itself.
In a book prefaced by Linus Torvalds, the creator of the famous program Linux,
the Finnish philosopher Pekka Himanen attempts to define an ethic of the
hacker community, of which the most elementary definition is of a ?passion
for programming?. The book is titled The Hacker Ethic and the Spirit of the
Information Era [in English it is published as The Hacker Ethic and the
Spirit of the New Economy -Translator] 5Scroll downwards, in reference to Max
Weber's book, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, written at
the beginning of the century, which developed the Marxist thesis according to
which Protestantism is a product of and a factor in the development of
capitalism. For Pekka Himanen, hackers, even if generally they do not claim
to destroy capitalism, are leading to the development of a series of general
conceptions which are the opposite of the Protestant ethic and thus that of
capitalism. In this manner, he writes: ?The radical nature of hackerism
consists in proposing an alternative spirit for networked society, a spirit
that puts the dominant Protestant ethic in question. In this context, it is
the only time when all hackers are crackers [programmers who introduce
themselves into big corporate sites and institutions to cause trouble, often
improperly called hackers]. They attempt to crack the steel safe. (...) There
is an inherent contradiction in the cohabitation of hackerism with a very
traditional capitalism. To begin with, the terms capitalist and hacker are of
very different senses. In harmony with the hankering of the Protestant ethic
after money, the supreme goal of capitalism is the accumulation of capital.
The hacker ethic of work, for its part, puts the accent on the activity,
centered around a passion and the free management of time.... The hacker work
ethic is a melange of passion and liberty. It is this aspect of the hacker
ethic that has had the most influence.? Or again: ?We have explained that
hackers oppose themselves to hierarchical management for ethical reasons,
because that could lead to a culture in which people are humiliated, but also
because they think that a nonhierarchical model is more effective.?
The author outlines in this manner, across a number of examples, the tableau
of a conception of development leading by its own logic-altruistic and eager
for effectiveness-to the direct detriment of the dominant, Protestant,
capitalist ideology. Himanen recognizes at the end of his essay that not all
hackers recognize themselves in his portrait. But he is certain that many
would.
As we have already said, this thinking inevitably contains contradictions,
product of the relations with the market world in which it germinates. And
few are the hackers who push the logic of this thinking to its final
subversive conclusions. But it is false to say, like JC claims, that this
logic places itself "entirely in the context of market capital." The critique
of market exchange and of money, the rejection of hierarchy and borders, the
critique of contemporary work and the revindication of passion and freedom as
primary motivations, of cooperation and of sharing as the foundations of new
relations, all this is found, to a degree more or less elaborated and
coherent, in the "hacker ethic." Now these are elements that form part of the
foundation of the communist project.
The idea of such a statement shocks many "Marxists," wrongly. The fact that
communist principles (even if incomplete) can be rediscovered from a
scientific approach confronted with the possibilities of new technologies,
without any explicit reference to Marxism and to communist theories of the
past, constitutes a spectacular verification of the Marxist idea according to
which communist ideas are not the product of the benevolent brains of certain
thinkers, but the fruit of the development of capitalist society itself.
Instead of them enclosing themselves in scornful ignorance of this reality,
consistent Marxists should get excited and encourage the tendencies that lead
hackerism to a radical critique of capital. Rosa Luxemburg said "the
objective logic of the historical process precedes the subjective logic of
the protagonists." It is urgent that coherent Marxists take note of the real
historical process which unfolds under their eyes, and that they assume their
responsibility of accelerating the subjective logic of the protagonists.
Before concluding this part on "the ideology of the founders of free
software," I want to say a word on a remark by JC, who wrote: "These
proclamations [of Raoul] are very close to those of certain free-software
activists. Like the members of Oekonux." 6Scroll downwards
I have not had the occasion to read all the documents on this site,
unfortunately because most of them are in German. I do not know up to what
point Stefan Merten, the most well-known of the members of Oekonux, could be
considered on the same level as most of the "free-software activists," as JC
says, in the measure in which he situates himself in an explicitly Marxist
optic. But, as far as I know,, it is certain that I share certain important
points of view with them, like the context of Marxist theory and the idea
that free software constitutes a germ of a new society: "In Oekonux there is
the idea that free software could be exactly that: an embryonic form of a new
society materialized in the midst of the old." 7Scroll downwards
But that leads into the second part of JC's critique and questions.
Germs of Non-market Relations
In the last part of his text, "by way of conclusion", JC poses "a general
question": "I wonder about the idea that, in the midst of capitalism, by way
of new technological developments, 'the germs of non-market relations' could
be born." And he responds in the negative. His argument is the following:
This idea that the economic (thus social) form of the future society could
develop itself in the interior of capitalist society is given by Raoul with
reference to Marx: ?new superior relations of production never replace older
ones before the material conditions for their existence have matured within
the framework of the old society.? I understand this phrase in the following
sense: The experience of forms of self-organization of the proletariat
(workers' councils) is the anticipation of the forms of organization of the
future society; and it is in the class struggle that the material conditions
of ?superior relations of production? will constitute themselves, blossoming
?within the framework of the old society.? As for that, we have learned
through experience that these forms cannot be permanent in the midst of
capitalist society; they are, if they do not win, only transitory and
fleeting.
Now, that which Raoul affirms seems to me to resemble the following: the
creation, not of forms of self-organization spawned by the class struggle,
but of non-market economic (thus social) forms in the midst of capitalism,
which, furthermore, tend to eternalize themselves. I think that what
characterizes the proletariat in comparison to the insurgent classes of
pre-capitalist periods, is precisely its extreme weakness, the fact that it
cannot support itself in the midst of capitalist society (contrary to the
bourgeoisie under feudalism) by its own economic forces.
If I respond negatively to this possibility of ?germs of non-market relations
in the midst of advanced capitalism,? via the particular example of free
software, I would tend to give a negative response, in general, to all
analogous possibilities of finding non-market (even as germs) relations in
capitalism.
What Marx and History Say
We begin by examining JC's interpretation of the famous citation in Marx's
preface to his Contribution to the Critique of Political EconomyRemote link,
before attempting to see what history itself says about the passage from one
social system to another.
JC thinks, when Marx speaks of "material conditions" that begin to "mature
within the old society" to permit the existence of "superior relations of
production," that it has to do with the more advanced social practice of the
proletariat in struggle in the midst of capitalism: the workers' councils. We
remark, first of all, that when Marx wrote these lines, neither workers'
councils - appearing for the first time in 1905 in Russia - nor even the
first form of that type of organization, such as that which surged forth
during the Paris Commune in 1871, existed. Of what "forms of
self-organization spawned by the class struggle" had Marx spoken? Note that
Marx did not seek to define a law concerning the passage from capitalism to
communism. He treated the succession of different modes of production,
"Asiatic, ancient, feudal, and bourgeois-modern," of which he said, "reduced
to their broad outlines," they "appear as progressive epochs of the economic
formation of society." What, for JC, are the "material conditions" in the
case of the other historical transitions?
When Marx, in the same text, treated the "disruptions" which characterized
these transitions, he wrote: "In studying such transformations it is always
necessary to distinguish between the material transformation of the economic
conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of
natural science, and the legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic
- in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict
and fight it out."
Without wanting to lose ourselves in exegetical exercises, one could, if need
be, say that JC's interpretation of the "material conditions" as the practice
of the struggle in "workers' councils," could be linked to the need to
"become conscious of this conflict" that must "be fought out". But, besides
the fact that this would mean a reduction of the "ideological" dimension of
reality, this interpretation ignores its economic dimension, "the material
transformation of the conditions of production." For Marx, as he explained
it, some lines before, in the same text, "the anatomy of civil society is to
be sought in political economy."
JC's interpretation of Marx's thinking on this question is, at the least, very
narrow. It is clear that when Marx spoke of the necessity that the "material
conditions" begin to mature in the midst of the old society, it had to do
essentially with the development of the material conditions of production, in
particular, the productive forces.
If one observes the history of two transitions in mode of production that one
knows the best: from ancient slavery to feudalism, and from feudalism to
capitalism, it appears clearly that the material conditions had unfolded in
the midst of the old society. What is more, this development permitted that
the new relations of production appeared, although in an embryonic form, by
taking their place in the midst and at the side of the old dominant relations
of production.
The development of the colonat, had under the Roman empire, in the 2d century,
an important acceleration, but it had to do with an already-ancient
phenomenon. In the 3d century, this mode of production, which established the
economic basis of feudal relations between exploiters and exploited, had
become a normal form of production on the great properties. The growth of
capitalism in the midst of feudalism also took place during centuries. Since
the 11th century, through the development of commerce, in particular in the
north of Western Europe and in the Mediterranean, capitalism had become an
economic reality in Flanders and in certain Italian cities. It took, however,
above all, a mercantile form, but not uniquely: By the 12th century, "the
arsenals of Venice constructed ships at a pace unknown till then." It was,
nevertheless, not until the 16th and 17th century, in England and France,
that the bourgeois, new masters of the economy, had the power to sever the
feudal kings' heads, allowing them to expand their affairs more freely. When
the bourgeoisie definitively conquered political power, it had for a long
time already had the power to economically dominate society. The political
revolution came at the end of the process of implantation of the economic
base of a new system in the midst of the old society.
In the case of past transitions, Marx's theory is easily verified and
comprehensible: Before the new society affirms its definitive domination, it
has already effectively affirmed that of its material base, economic in the
first place; this has blossomed in the midst of the old society.
But it's much more complex when it has to do with envisioning the transition
from capitalism to communism. For the past, at least in the cases we have
seen, the coexistence of the two modes of production is facilitated by the
fact that they both have to do with systems based on the exploitation of one
part of society by another. In the late Roman empire, the slave-masters and
the masters of the coloni were often the same people. In feudalism, the
relations between the seigniors (nobles, ecclesiasticals) and the bourgeoisie
were often bloody. The wars of religion - which, behind the confrontation
between the new Protestant "ethic" and Catholicism, set tendencies favorable
to the new capitalist-market values in opposition to old feudal structures -
were a murderous and dramatic instance. In spite of that, the coexistence
between the new system and the old was facilitated by the fact that it
concerned modes of exploitation, with the dominant classes always ready to
get along on the backs of the exploited. In numerous cases, the aristocratic
powers of the old regime would easily metamorphosize themselves into rich
capitalists, not even losing any of their old [feudal] privileges. The
political revolutions that marked the accession of the bourgeoisie to state
power did not always and everywhere have to take the radical forms they did
in England and France.
But, in the case of the accession to communism, it has to do with passing from
a system of exploitation to a new society without classes or exploitation.
For Marxists, the class that bears the new society, the proletariat, is the
class that produces most of economic wealth, but it produces them according
to relations of production that subordinate it. This class cannot engender
new social relations of production in accord with its essential interests,
the elimination of all exploitation, without destroying the political
framework that reduces it to impotence. Contrary to revolutionary classes of
the past, its political revolution does not come at the end of a process of
economic implantation, but must, on the contrary, constitute the initial act
permitting the transformation of the material conditions of production. When
Marx spoke of the material conditions that have to mature under capitalism to
permit the proletariat to introduce communist relations, it's not about the
germs of these relations but fundamentally about a sufficient degree of
development and deployment of the productive forces under capitalist
relations of production.
That is, or has generally been, up to the present, the Marxist view of the
question. On that level, it's also what JC reproduces in his text, at least
when he writes: "I think that what characterizes the proletariat in
comparison to the insurgent classes of pre-capitalist periods, is precisely
its extreme weakness, the fact that it cannot support itself in the midst of
capitalist society (contrary to the bourgeoisie under feudalism) by its own
economic forces." I myself have always defended this position in the past.
However, the new technological reality and the appearance of the world of
free software, which was driven by it, weaken, in my opinion, this point of
view. It is certain that the idea that germs of new relations of production
of a non-market type, containing communist elements, could arise and
"eternalize themselves," to use JC's term, in the midst of capitalism,
contradicts a part, an aspect, of Marxist theory.
"Germs"?
But, before going further, it is indispensable to explain what one means by
"relations of production" and by "germs" of relations of production. Because
one could object that the relations that link the creators of free software
to one another and then them to the users - who participate or not in its
creation - cannot be considered true social relations of production, that is
to say, relations that could be generalized to the whole of productive social
activity, as was the case for feudalism or capitalism in the past. The
material capacity of being freely reproduced is possible only for goods that
are digitizable, transformable into a line of numbers and characters. We have
seen already how that is the case for a number of means of production, like
software to run machines, or consumption goods, like films, games or music.
But, for the moment, we don't know how to digitize alimentary goods, nor raw
materials, for example. How can such relations, which touch only a very
narrow part of society and materially concern only a very specific category
of goods in means of production and consumption, be considered social
relations, or even germs of social relations? The creators of free software
cannot nourish themselves with software, nor turn them into products for
sale, because by definition it is free. How to socialize relations that don't
nourish their people?
If one looks at past history, though, in particular the birth of capitalist
relations during feudalism, or if one attempts to project history into the
future, and, more specifically, the place that digitizable goods could be
called to take in the process of social production, two conclusions impose
themselves, which permit a glimpse of how relations introduced by free
software could become socially dominant relations of production.
Venetian merchants, who had made their fortunes in the midst of feudalism by
selling arms or luxury goods from Asia to European feudal seigniors, did not
constitute the heart of social production. Even if they brought to the
narrowness of feudal life - centered around the fief and its village church -
an opening to world commerce (the courtesans of the European courts could
wear robes made of Oriental products), the relations among the merchants and
between them and the rest of the feudal world remained marginal, and would
appear to be purely subsidiary. The production of essential, indispensable
goods for the subsistence of men (agricultural goods and artisan ones,
principally), was performed under feudal relations. This marginal, secondary
aspect of capitalist relations in the midst of feudal society was so
self-evident that even in the 18th century, the first bourgeois economists,
the French Physiocrats, could, without laughing, pretend that merchants and
manufacturers should not pay taxes because they do not create any true "net
product": They do nothing but transport it or modify its form.
What do we want to deduce? That from their birth, in the midst of the old
society, the superior relations of production, were not obligatorily born
with a complete form, capable of managing the totality of social production,
nor even its most vital part. The fact that, today, free software and, more
generally, digitizable goods concern no more than a part, again, marginal, of
social production and consumption, does not constitute any argument showing
the impossibility that the economic relations that they induce will not one
day become the dominant social relations.
That which has permitted capitalist relations to become dominant after
centuries of existence is not only the ideological, military, and political
victory of the bearers of the new capitalist values against the old feudal
regime, even if they have played a determining role, but the material,
concrete fact - which demonstrates daily and by methods more and more evident
- that the new relations were the only ones that could permit the use of new
productive forces engendered by the opening of commerce and the development
of production techniques. "In the last instance," it is the economic
imperative, the irreversible historical tendency to the development of labor
productivity, that finishes by imposing its own law.
That which today permits one to envision the possibility that relations of
production founded on the principles of free software (production with a view
toward satisfying the needs of the community, sharing, cooperation, the
elimination of market exchange) could become socially dominant is the fact
that these relations are the most able to employ the new techniques of
information and communication, and that the recourse to these techniques,
their place in the social process of production, can only grow, ineluctably.
The world of free software does not constitute a microcosm of truly complete
new social relations. Certain of its products begin to take a significant
place in the social process of production: the informatics infrastructure of
the Internet, recourse by the most important producers of computers and state
institutions to Linux, etc. However, the producers of free software are not
nourished by their own product. The "gratuitistic" logic is not generalized
yet to the goods that assure the material subsistence of the producers. Those
who work for free or are paid by an enterprise to create free software remain
dependent on the revenues provided by the market world. In this sense, just
like the capitalist relations in in their time, the relations induced by the
logic of free software can be nothing but the "germs" of social relations.
Insufficiency and Validity of Marxism
Marx and Engels could not have foreseen such a reality. Even under the form of
"germs", they would have dismissed all possibility of the appearance of new
economic relations in the midst of capitalism without a revolutionary
transformation. At most, to temper this statement, one could cite Marx's
considerations in the International Workingmen's Association, ? propos the
cooperatives that expressed the spirit of a great majority of the workers'
movement regrouped within the First International. In a resolution adopted by
the first congress in Geneva in 1866, edited by Marx, it is written: "(a) We
recognize the cooperative movement as a transformative force of the present
society, founded on the antagonism of classes. Its great merit is to show
practically that the current system of subordination of labor to capital,
despotic and pauperizing, could be supplanted by the republican system of the
free and equal association of the producers." However, the same resolution,
against all illusions, questioned that: "(b) But the cooperative system,
limited to the form of minuscule results of the individual efforts of wage
slaves, is impotent to transform capitalist society on its own. To convert
social production into a large and harmonious system of cooperative labor,
general changes are indispensable." 8Scroll downwards One knows that Marx did
not entertain any illusions about the future of cooperatives as a passage to
new social relations, as this resolution itself shows, or his Inaugural
Address of the International Workingmen's Association, in which he states
that "this cooperation will never be able to stop the monopolies that grow in
geometrical progression." History gives good reason. Just like it condemns
theories of the possibility of "socialism in one country," the mainstay of
Stalinist lies.
The reality of free software situates itself on another terrain, or in another
dimension. It is not a geographically circumscribed reality. It cannot be
reduced to a change in the relations in the midst of or within a given
community, since its principal characteristic, the gratuiticity of its
products, concerns the entirety of society. Contrary to cooperatives, which
must sell their products on the market, and thus sooner or later submit to
the imperatives of the market, free software is freely accessible to all. The
original character of the relations free software induces are caused
fundamentally by the unusual nature of the informatics and informational
goods that permit the creation of means of production and consumption freely
reproducible on a planetary level. It's about a new reality that neither Marx
nor Engels, nor any of the Marxists of most of the 20th century, either
recognized or foresaw.
What's so surprising about the fact that the Marx's and Engels's vision,
defined in an epoch in which mail circulated in large part by means of
horses, must be modified, adapted to the age of planetary e-mail? Marx and
Engels, who followed, with passion, the very least development of the
sciences and techniques of their time in order to research all that could
possibly contribute to facilitating the introduction of communist society,
certainly could not have acted otherwise, and would, correctly, have been
enthusiastic about the development of the Internet and free software.
Contrary to the vision of an invariant Marxism that has already foreseen
everything and contains no possible shortcoming, whatever the development of
capitalism, Marx and Engels always stayed true to their critique of dogmatic
religious thought: They knew that the role of theory is not to deny or to
ignore facts that contradict it, but to enrich itself with these new
elements, knowing to question itself, to better develop its explanatory and
revolutionary power.
If Marxism has not specifically foreseen the possibility of the appearance of
"germs" of non-market relations in the midst of capitalism, and thus finds
itself contradicted in a particular aspect, the phenomenon of free software
constitutes by that same token a screaming verification of the more general
and fundamental aspects of Marxist theory.
As one has seen in the first part of this text, the principles that preside
over the logic of free software contain important elements of communist
theory. And as it has already been implied, the fact that these principles
would be able to be rediscovered in the appearance of a new technology
represents a confirmation of the Marxist idea that sees in communist
principles, not an ideal invented by any big thinkers, but the product of the
evolution of society itself. On a more general plane, at the level of the
dynamic of history, the fact that the development of production technologies
under capitalism has managed to engender an economic sector that
intrinsically tends to escape the law of value and that develops itself in
the very heart of the process of social production, gives a new material
substance to the idea according to which capitalism could not be surpassed by
anything but a social organization abolishing market exchange.
New Questions
Denying the existence of germs of new social relations in the midst of
capitalism in the name of Marxism would be to betray the spirit of the same
by upholding the letter. I, for one, believe that the Marxist theoretical
framework constitutes the best tool to respond to the crucial questions that
this new reality poses, and that research in this domain constitutes a
priority, if not the priority, for the revolutionaries of our time.
The questions are numerous and important. They can be grouped into two,
interdependent, dimensions: those of the relations between free software and
the capitalist economy, in which it emerged, on the one hand; and those of
its relation to the class struggle, on the other.
On the economic level: Up to what point could current cooperation between free
software and the market economy go, without negative consequences at the
level of the profitability and the realization of capital making themselves
felt? Up to what point will go the antagonism between the growing desire of
government to protect copyright for commercial software and the also-growing
tendency toward "piratage" of digital goods? How long will it take before the
share of the digitizable means necessary for the production of alimentary
goods or raw materials is sufficiently important for the production cost of
those goods to be almost completely eliminated by simple recourse to free
software? On the level of class struggle, how long will it take for the
reality of free software and its principles to be known by all the exploited?
Would the defense of these principles end up being a direct object of
confrontation with the state? What modifications in the daily class struggle
would the knowledge of or participation in a practical model of a new type of
social relations entail? The practical example of free software would have a
power of conviction incomparably more important and effective than that, in
their time, of the utopians of the 19th century, from Owens's New Harmony and
Fourrier's phalansteries to the spirit of the cooperatives. 9Scroll downwards
How, in these conditions, can "the period of transition" to communism be
envisioned?
It took centuries for the germs of capitalist relations, in the 11th and 12th
centuries, to become the socially dominant mode of production. The history of
our time has not unfolded with the same speed, and the historical situations
are very different. Barring the self-destruction of humanity (unfortunately,
possible) by some sort of skidding out of control of capitalist barbarity,
the generalization of the principles of free software to the whole of
productive social processes (elimination of market exchange, production as a
function of the good of the community, cooperation, and sharing) could take
much less time. That depends on the speed and the intensity of an objective
material historical process, but also on the consciousness that people have
of the existent conflict and the necessity of "fighting it out."
For those, like JC, who want to be able to participate in the dynamic of this
grasping for consciousness, the recognition of the new historical situation
created by the development of "new technology" is an indispensable step. It
is inevitable if we want to respond to the important and multiple questions
that modern circumstances thrust upon us. 10Scroll downwards
Original version written October 2002
1Scroll upwards "The GNU GPL and the American Way," 2001.
2Scroll upwards One can find this text of the GNU Manifesto at
http://www.gnu.org/gnu/manifesto.htmlRemote link.
3Scroll upwards This reality explains in part the different forms of
non-proprietary software that distinguish themselves by the degree of their
gratuiticity, or liberty accorded to the user. In the strict sense, the term
"free software" designates in reality only one specific type "protected" by
the GNU GPL. One can find more details in the book JC cites, Logiciels libres
(Free Software) (Edispher), by JP Smets-Solanes and Beno?t Frachon.
4Scroll upwards ?Free Software and the GPL Society,? interview with Stefan
Merten, by Joanne Richardson, November 2001.
http://subsol.c3.hu/subsol_2/contributors0/mertentext.htmlRemote link.
5Scroll upwards L'?thique hacker et l'esprit de l'?re de l'information; Exils
Editeurs, 2001.
6Scroll upwards www.oekonux.orgLocal link
7Scroll upwards Interview with Stefan Merten, April 24, 2001.
8Scroll upwards Karl Marx, Oeuvres, volume I, p. 1469 (Editions La Pleiade,
1963).
9Scroll upwards In the course of our conference on June 15, in discussion on
the theme of technological revolution, Mazagan responded to me: "I think that
Raoul, in the current situation of class struggle, seeks a deus ex machina
that could bring us comfort". I often wonder about that myself. But this
question only concerns an argument about the subjectivity that would form a
thought. It has nothing to say about the objective content of the thought.
Does an analysis have to be contrary to the subjectivity of whomever defends
it in order to be correct? Would, then, the idea of a communist society be
false because it "brings comfort" to those who live under capitalism? It is
true that, for those who claimed to see the premises of a world communist
revolution in the extraordinary development of proletarian class struggle in
the course of the period from the end of the 1960s to the beginning of the
1980s, the profound and general recoil of this combativity over the course of
the following two decades has constituted an often devastating deception. But
instead of lamenting over our situation, which would need of "comfort," it is
much more useful to attempt to respond to the question of knowing why, in
this struggle which, in certain cases, mobilized a near-totality of the
proletariat of certain countries (France 1968, Poland 1980), often attaining
a degree of confrontation with the state of a violence unknown for decades,
the combatants never joined a movement giving itself, explicitly, the goal of
the construction of a post-capitalist, communist society. Historical
realities never have a single cause. But among the reasons that explain this
"self-limitation" of the class movement must certainly be the difficulty of
collectively perceiving what a post-capitalist society could be. The
"revolutionary project," as it was discussed at the instigation of the more
radical elements, was nebulous, opaque, and sometimes terrifying. The Soviet
model, with all its variants, from the Chinese "Cultural Revolution" to the
guerrilla centers of Latin America, by way of the sinister Albania,
pronounced as a model by some Maoists, haunted all minds and paralyzed many.
Even if these struggles marked a historical rupture vis-?-vis the enormous
influence of the Stalinist currents on the wage workers in a number of
countries, this distance was only the beginning. Inevitably, all discussion
of the revolutionary project began with debates on the qualities, or not, of
"communist" countries or those "on the way to communism," etc. And when one
attempted to go beyond them, the impression that one was spouting pious and
abstract dreams weighed on one as a source of doubt. It would be a mistake to
underestimate the lack, the crying insufficiency of the revolutionary project
to explain the weakness of past proletarian struggles. The new technologies
and the logic of free software that they have engendered constitute
determinant new elements on which to found this project much more concretely.
10Scroll upwards The question of knowing whether the material conditions of
communism existed or not before the current technological revolution is an
important question for the analysis of historical dynamics of the past. But
whatever one's response to this question, it is a priority to confirm that
contemporary technological transformations carry material conditions that
facilitate, in a qualitatively new manner, the construction of a communist
society.
NavigationLocal link | SitemapLocal link | HomeLocal link
http://www.oekonux.org/ texts/marketrelations.htmlRemote link
Contact: Projekt-TeamMail link, Last Changed: 17.02.03
--
Jeebesh Bagchi
Sarai/CSDS
29 Rajpur Road
Delhi 110054
Ph: 91 11 23960040
More information about the commons-law
mailing list